Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
Ralph Allan Smith
Cornelius Van Til may have been the most
important evangelical Trinitarian thinker in the 20th century, but his work has not at all received the
attention it deserves. No doubt one reason for this neglect was the fact that Van Til’s rather difficult approach
to apologetics occupied the center of
the stage. Amidst controversy about the transcendental argument, epistemology,
and questions like whether or not
Christians and non-Christians share common ground, the Trinitarian center of Van Til’s apologetics seems
to have gone unnoticed. It may be added, too, that his formula for the Trinity — one Person, three Persons — was
dismissed out of hand by some because
it struck them as a plain contradiction. Finally, Van Til’s trinitarianism
perhaps did not attract the
attention it should have because it suffered from a lack of full development in
Van Til. Though the doctrine of the
Trinity is at the core of all that Van Til wrote, one might still say that rather than offering a full-bodied
Trinitarian theology, he offered the foundations upon which such a theology might be built. Van Til blazed trails,
leaving it up to those after him to
build the highways and cities.
Van Til’s contribution touches at least five
general areas. First, Van Til offered a basic and general statement of Trinitarianism, supplementing
the traditional formula. Second, Van Til related the doctrine of the Trinity to the Greek philosophical problem
of the one and the many. Third, Van
Til taught a doctrine of knowledge that is distinctly Trinitarian. Fourth, Van
Til claims that the doctrine of the
Trinity is the Biblical foundation for a properly Christian approach to apologetics. Fifth, Van Til suggests a covenant
relationship among the persons of the Trinity. These five general areas do not exhaust Van Til’s contribution, but
they do show that Van Til was an
original Trinitarian thinker who offered a truly Reformed — because
emphatically Biblical (Sola
Scriptura) and theological (Soli Deo Gloria) — approach to
systematic theology and the Christian
worldview.
Trinitarian
Formulas
John Frame was the first
theologian to draw attention to Van Til’s suggested reformulation of the
doctrine of the Trinity, though Van Til himself stated his view relatively
clearly. Frame refers to it as a “very bold
theological move,” but a few have regarded it as heresy or something very
close. What did Van Til suggest that was either “bold” or “heretical”? Van Til
spoke of God as “a one-conscious being” and also “a tri-conscious
being.”1 At the point where this observation
is introduced, however, its full implications are not stated. Rather, Van Til
offers Biblical justification for the doctrine of the Trinity
and an extended discussion of the statement of
the doctrine in Church history, noting contributions by Calvin and Bavinck in
particular, and treating the important Church
fathers and creeds.
1 An Introduction
to Systematic Theology (Phillipsburg,
NJ: Presbyterian and Reformed, 1971), p. 220.
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
Though this discussion is
heavily dependent upon Charles and Alexander Hodge, Benjamin
Warfield, and Herman Bavinck, Van Til does not fail to offer his own very
penetrating observations.
1. He notes that the
procession of the Spirit must be from both Father and Son in order that the three persons may be understood as
wholly co-ordinate and so that the inter-communion
of the persons may be complete. The Spirit proceeds eternally from the Father to the Son and from the Son to the
Father. Eternal procession, thus, corresponds
to eternal generation and with the doctrine of eternal generation offers a Trinitarianism in which the intercommunication and
co-ordination of the three Persons is
complete.2
2. In an interesting
restatement of Schaff’s explanation of the heresies that the early creeds opposed, Van Til notes that “all heresies
with respect to the Trinity may be reduced
to the one great heresy of mixing the eternal with the temporal.”3
This leads to a very remarkable statement: “God exists as triune. He is
therefore self-complete. Yet he
created the world. This world has meaning not in spite of, but because
of, the self-completeness of the
ontological Trinity. This God is the foundation of the created universe and therefore is far above it.
If he were defined only as the negation of the universe, without first being thought of as its foundation, we
would have an absolute otherness of God. But this ‘absolute otherness’ would in
the end become an aspect of reality
as a whole, when brought into relation with the temporal universe at all. Any doctrine that denies God’s providence (as
deism does) or his providence and creation (as Greek thought did) must in the
end become a confusion of the eternal
and the temporal. Deism and pantheism are not more than two forms of the one basic error of confusion of the eternal and
the temporal."4
3.
Van Til emphasizes Calvin’s doctrine of the
Trinity. His discussion here is dependent
on Warfield’s analysis of the history of Trinitarian theology and Calvin’s contribution. Warfield pointed out that Calvin’s
emphasis on the “autothetes” (self-existence) of the Son undermined the tendency to subordinationism, a
tendency that came to expression in
Arminian theology. Another observation borrowed from Warfield’s exposition of Calvin is equally
fascinating: “According to Calvin, then, it would seem, there can be no such thing as a monadistic God; the idea of
mutiformity enters into the very
notion of God.”5 Van Til, following Calvin, insists that God must be a Trinity in order to be God and that the
Three Persons must be equally ultimate.
4. On
modernism Van Til comments, “Modernism is the happy heir of all the heresies
and basic to all its heresies is the denial of the consubstantiality of the Son
and the Spirit with the Father. Or rather, its error is
even deeper than that, since the
2 Ibid., p. 226.
3 Ibid.
4 Ibid. p. 227.
5 Ibid., p. 223, quoting from Warfied’s Calvin and Calvinism, p.
191.
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
Father
himself is for Modernism no more than an aspect of reality. If ever there was a
need for re-affirming and teaching the true doctrine of the Trinity, it is
now.”6
What is important for our discussion here is to
note that in his lengthy explanation of the basis and history of the doctrine, it is very clear that Van Til
wholeheartedly agrees with the tradition
formulations of the doctrine of the Trinity. He is not proposing a new formula
to replace the Church tradition.7
In that sense, then, Van Til cannot be legitimately charged with teaching
heresy, for he most enthusiastically confesses the doctrine of the creeds.
He adds to it, however, his own formulation.
Before we consider that formula, we may ask, if he is satisfied with the Creeds of the Church, why add? Van Til
himself offers us a hint at his motivation
when he speaks of the addition of the filioque by the Western Church.
“If the true doctrine was to be
maintained it had to be continually restated and refined.”8 A few
years have passed since Athanasius and Augustine refined the Nicene doctrine.
Our modern (postmodern) world
presents it own unique challenges, which means we must continually restate the
doctrine in language that clarifies its application to our own time. That is
essentially what Van Til was doing.
The Enlightenment challenged the authority of the
Bible and denied that faith in the Biblical
God was the true starting point and ultimate standard for human knowledge. Van
Til had to address the modern West
and its pretended intellectual autonomy. One of the foundations of that intellectual autonomy, though Van Til
does not refer to it in his discussion of the Trinity, is the theory of evolution, which stands behind
the modern view of the world. The origin and movement of the universe depend
upon impersonal forces. If there is unity, it is in an abstract impersonal law or principle that sums up the
so-called “laws of nature.” Van Til points out the deeper motivation behind the Enlightenment and
evolutionary approaches to knowledge. Sinful men try to escape from the notion of an absolute personality because of
the obvious implications it has for
the individual. Extraterrestrial intelligence, vastly superior to man’s, is
permissible, whether it is understood
as harmless and cute, as in Spielberg’s ET, or as malevolent, as in some of the X-Files. In contrast with the notion of
absolute personality, extraterrestrial superior intelligence does not imply that man is comprehensively responsible and
therefore must stand before God’s
throne. Absolute personality implies that all of man’s life is under authority
and judgment. This is the offense of
the Trinity.
To
state the doctrine of the Trinity in terms that bring its offense clearly to
the fore, Van Til claims that we must not merely confess that God is one Being
and three Persons, we must also affirm that God is one Person and
three Persons. The challenge to the Gospel in our day is the attempt to claim an ultimate impersonalism, to
find the unity of the world in an impersonal principle or formula (or to deny unity altogether). To show the
Christian God to our generation, we
need to make the full implications of Nicene transparent. God is not “one
Being” in the sense that there is some sort of impersonal substratum underling
and unifying the three Persons. God’s being
cannot be thought of as an impersonal principle without denying the reality of
the God of the Bible. He is
thoroughly personal. Thus Van Til claims,
6 Ibid., p. 228.
7 John
Frame comments, “I suspect that Van Til himself would have claimed that these
creeds taught his view implicitly; he certainly was
not conscious of rejecting anything in them, and I do not believe that he did
reject any of their Trinitarian doctrine.” Cornelius Van Til:
An Analysis of His Thought (Phillipsburg, NJ: Presbyterian and
Reformed, 1995), p. 66.
8 Introduction to Systematic Theology, p. 225.
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
We do assert that God, that is,
the whole Godhead, is one person. We have noted how each attribute is
co-extensive with the being of God. We are compelled to maintain
this in order to avoid the notion of an uninterpreted being of some sort. In
other words, we are bound to maintain the identity of the attributes of God
with the being of God in order to avoid the specter of brute fact.
In a similar manner we have noted how theologians insist that each of the
persons of the Godhead is co-terminous with
the being of the Godhead. But all this is not to say that the distinctions of
the attributes are merely nominal. Nor is it to say that the
distinctions of the persons are merely nominal. We need both the absolute
cotermineity of each attribute and each person
with the whole being of God, and the genuine significance of the distinctions of
the attributes and the persons.9
It is apparent that Van Til is re-stating the
traditional doctrine with modern concerns in mind. He fears any statement of the doctrine of God that allows the
impersonal and ultimately mysterious
to find room in the infinite expanse of God’s being and therefore reminds us
that there is nothing in God which
is not wholly interpreted and wholly comprehended by the Persons of the Trinity. God’s attributes are each
co-extensive with His being. Also, the three Persons of the Trinity cannot be thought of as coming
together into one in an impersonal manner. For if the oneness of God were impersonal, then the
impersonal would transcend the personal and in some sense be mysterious
to the three Persons themselves, with the result that the fully self-comprehending and self-complete God of the Bible
would be denied. It is in the interest of preserving the truth of God as wholly personal, wholly rational and
wholly transcendent that Van Til adds
that we must think of His oneness as personal oneness rather than as abstract
being.
The full and complete intercommunication of the Persons
of the Trinity is necessary to this complete
personal self-integration, so, contrary to the Eastern Church, the Holy Spirit
must be understood as proceeding from both Father and Son. Confession of
the aseity of the Son and the Spirit
is essential to the full ontological equality of the three persons, without
which subordinationism and/or the
specter of the impersonal monad threaten. The absolute personality of God must be seen as the ultimate foundation of
all that is created in order to truly confess Him as Creator and to maintain the ultimate
rationality of the world. Thus, all of Van Til’s observations on the doctrine of the Trinity referred to above tend in
the same direction, to shield the
truth of God against every possibility of the invasion of the impersonal and
irrational. Van Til’s formula one
Person, three Persons, therefore, is the kind of refined restatement of the
truth which he regarded as necessary
for the preservation of the truth. There is nothing here even remotely heretical in substance. Only
misunderstanding or perverse adherence to the form of words while neglecting their substance can find
theological error. Van Til’s formula provides for our day a desperately needed and important refinement of the
traditional doctrine.
John Frame points out that Van Til’s formula is
Scriptural, since the Bible does speak of God Himself as a person without specifying one of the three Persons.10
He also explains that an approach which asserts that God is one Person
and also three Persons would only be a contradiction
if the word “person” means precisely the same thing in each case. But that is
not the case. There is a distinction between the personhood of God as one and
the personhood of God as three. Thus, the formula one person, three persons is
not a logical contradiction. Nor is
9 Ibid., p. 229.
10 Op. Cit., p. 69.
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
the equivocation on the word
“person” problematic, for the statement of the doctrine itself is not a
link in a logical chain. What is the precise difference between the meaning of
the word “person” as it refers to the one Person of God and the
three Persons? Frame excuses himself from responsibility to answer.11
If that bothers the reader, Frame points out that in the history of the
doctrine of the Trinity neither the terms hypostasis, ousia nor substantia
have been precisely defined. As far as the meaning
of the terms hypostasis and ousia in Greek, they are virtually synonymous.
Thus, though the Church chose to confess one ousia and three hypostases,
it could have reversed the words and confessed, one hypostasis
and three ousia. To make matters even more
confusing, the Latin formula multiplies the ambiguity. The Latin Church
confessed that God was one substantia
but the Latin substantia is closer to hypostasis than to ousia.
Thus, we might say that in the West God is “one substance” and in
the East, God is “three substances.”
The point of all of this is not
to fault the traditional doctrine of the Trinity. On the contrary, Frame
is affirming it, while reminding the reader that, “We cannot say precisely or
exhaustively how ousia in God differs from hypostasis, or prosopon,
or, for that matter, substantia or persona. . . . we are not equipped by revelation to
dissect the Trinity or to perform any quasi-scientific, minute analysis of it. Scripture tells us that God is one,
that the three are fully God, and
that they enter into various personal relationships with one another. From
these teachings we may draw implications and applications, up to a point. But
there is a point at which our reason
must admit its weakness and simply bow before God’s majesty.”12 How
could it be otherwise if the God of
the Bible is the absolute Person Scripture declares Him to be?
The One and the Many
Van Til is perhaps the first
theologian to explicitly relate the doctrine of the Trinity to the Greek
philosophical problem of the one and the many.13 To illustrate the
problem, he refers to the ancient Greek philosophers
Parmenides and Heraclites. For Parmenides only the unchanging is
real and fit to be an object of knowledge. Change is mere superficial
appearance. Underlying all change is the changeless and
really real. Ultimately, every diverse form is an aspect of the one
underlying and true reality. However, for his rival, Heraclites, all is flux.
War and strife are the basic realities. There is no
substratum. Nothing underlies the appearance of constant change that
confronts us in the world of our experience. The everlasting flow of all things
is the whole and only reality. The problem, then, is, what is
really real? What is the nature of reality? Is reality
ultimately a static one? Or, is reality ultimately the constantly changing
many?
Van Til explains the problem in
opting for either of these views.
11 Ibid.
12 Ibid., p. 70.
13
Colin Gunton certainly did not derive from Van Til his doctrine of the Trinity
as the solution to the problem of the one and the many,
even though he explains the Greek background of the problem by reference to Parmenides
and Heraclites, just as Van Til does. It seems so natural to relate the Trinity
to the one and the many that I suspect that one might find
other theologians in church history offering at least the seeds of such an
approach. For Colin Guntun’s very well-stated argument of this point, see: The
One, the Three and the Many: God, Creation, and
the Culture of Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1993). As before, I am indebted to John Frame
for the discussion of this aspect of Van Til’s Trinitarianism. Op. Cit., pp. 71
ff.
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
The many must be brought
into contact with one another. But how do we know that they
can be bought into contact with one another? How do we know that the many do
not simply exist as unrelated particulars? The answer given is that in such a
case we should know nothing of them; they would be abstracted
from the body of knowledge that we have; they
would be abstract particulars. On the other hand, how is
it possible that we should obtain a unity that does not destroy the
particulars? We seem to get our unity by
generalizing, by abstracting from the particulars in order to include
them into larger unities. If we keep up this process of generalization till we exclude
all the particulars, granted they can all be excluded, have we not stripped these
particulars of their particularity? Have we then obtained anything but an abstract
universal?14
We can restate this in simple terms with a
concrete example. If the many are ultimate, then knowledge is impossible, for knowledge depends upon the unifying power
of words. Every word expresses a unity of some sort. The word “dog,” for
example, brings together many particular
“dogs” into a single group and identifies them as a God-created group. If each
and every dog were independent
without relation to the whole, we could not know anything about dogs in general. If the many were
ultimate, we could not know anything about anything, for every word that we use — verbs, nouns, adjectives
and adverbs alike — all presuppose the idea that there are categories, unities. Thus, even if we gave up on the idea
of speaking about dogs and decided only to try to speak about Rover, what could
we say? Rover is brown. What is brown?
When we predicate brownness of Rover is that similar to brownness when we
predicate it of another dog? Is predication itself the same kind of thing when
we speak of another dog? Clearly the many
must be able to be brought into some sort of relation to one another in order
for knowledge to be possible.
By the same token, however, the many must
also be distinguishable. If we say that the one is ultimate, then whatever may be said about
Rover or about dogs is not really real. Rover is an aspect of something larger,
and not just the category dog. For dogs and stars and hot dogs are all just different aspects and manifestations of the
one really real reality. Whatever we say about Rover, therefore, is only meaningful or relevant insofar as it is
relatable to that ultimate one. We see once again, however, that language breaks down. For just as each
word is a unity, each word must also
be distinguishable from other words in order to bear meaning. When all things dissolve into the one, words bear no
meaning and knowledge is impossible.
Van Til pointed out that in the
Christian doctrine of the Trinity there is a solution to this fundamental
metaphysical dilemma, which lies at the heart of every philosophical problem in
the history of Western thought. In God, the three are
not more ultimate than the one and the one is not
more ultimate than the three. God was not first one and then three,
or first three and then one.
The one and the three are perfectly and wholly expressed and
integrated. Neither does God’s threeness compromise His oneness, nor does His
oneness compromise His threeness. God’s oneness and threeness are
equally ultimate and perfectly integrated in absolute harmony. God
Himself in His Triune glory is the Christian “theory of everything,” the final
answer to each and every dilemma of human
thought.
There
is a sense in which this seems obvious. If the one and the many is a problem,
and if God is both one and three,
then obviously God is the solution. However, for whatever reasons,
14 Van Til, Defense of the Faith,
p. 25-26, quoted in John Frame, Op. Cit., p. 71.
Van Til’s Insights
on the Trinity
this has not been emphasized in
the history of Trinitarianism, and the result is that the doctrine of the
Trinity has not seemed relevant. Van Til, by relating the doctrine of the Trinity
to the problem of the one and the many, clearly places the
doctrine of the Trinity at the foundation and center
of all thought about any and every subject. And, since the doctrine of the
Trinity itself is a mystery that can only be known
through Scripture, the harmony of the created one and many also
transcend our ability to discern by mere human reason. Thus, it is through
special revelation in Scripture that the harmony of
the one and the many for human society, too, can be properly understood.
In this way, Van Til ties Trinitarianism to revelation not only for the
knowledge of God but also for the Christian life.
Here is where Van Til’s insight really pays off.
If the ultimate solution to the problem of the one and the many is something that transcends our understanding and
can only be known through God’s
special revelation of Himself, then we should not be surprised if we must turn
to the Scriptures and the
commandments of God to find the practical, everyday solution to the many different ways concerns of unity and
individuality come into conflict. The temporal one and many find harmony only in the revelation given by
the God who is Himself the eternal One and Many. Christian social theory and ethics are tied to the Bible because
only in faithful obedience to God’s
special revelation can we realize the harmony of the one and many. God
transcends our understanding. We
cannot fathom the full meaning of the harmony of the one and many in God. We can only confess the truth that is revealed in Scripture.
In the same way, there are no basic principles
from which we can deduce the harmony of the one and many in human society. What
we need is detailed concrete
revelation of God’s will and the Holy Spirit of God, guiding us in wisdom to
apply God’s word to our situation.
The doctrine of the Trinity in Van Til,
therefore, is profoundly practical. The fact that everything in the world in one way or another is
related to the problem of the one and the many means that Trinitarianism is the
most applicable doctrine of all. Every issue, every debate, every daily activity is part of a larger whole and must
be seen to fit into some greater scheme of meaning for it to have meaning. At the same time, any larger view must
be applicable to the particulars or truth dissolves in an abstract one. With
the Bible itself as our standard for applying the implications of Trinitarian ethics to daily life, we have a
perspective that is both concrete and specific
while at the same time linked to a larger and comprehensive vision.
Trinity, Incomprehensibility,
Analogy, and Logic
Van Til understood the doctrine
of the Trinity as the center of Christian theology and philosophy.
The whole project of human knowing is inescapably a project of man conforming
to God, man’s knowledge and thinking conforming to God’s
knowledge and revelation. This leads in two apparently different
directions at once. On the one hand, revelation from God means that knowledge
is possible. On the other hand, because God is a Trinity and therefore
ultimately incomprehensible to us, we confront a paradoxical and apparently
contradictory reality. If we cannot fully comprehend God, it
follows that we will not be able to fully comprehend His plan either.
Both Van Til’s emphasis on knowledge as logical and systematic and his emphasis
on the limitations of logic and deduction come from his
Trinitarianism.
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
Incomprehensibility
All orthodox Christians agree that God is
incomprehensible. It is crucial to our very conception of God. But not all orthodox Christians agree on what it means
that God is incomprehensible. For Van
Til, affirming God’s incomprehensibility is essential to maintaining a proper
distinction between God and the creature. This means that for him, the
distinction between the knowledge of God and that of man is qualitative.
In contrast, another Reformed thinker,
Gordon Clark, charged that Van Til’s understanding of God’s incomprehensibility
leads to skepticism since man’s knowledge is only “like” God’s knowledge not
identical to God’s knowledge. For
Clark, the difference between the knowledge of God and that of man is better described as qualitative. God knows more
than man, but when both man and God know some truth, their knowledge must be identical in order for them to be both
knowing the same thing. The
difference between Clark’s concern about the problems of skepticism and Van
Til’s concern with preserving the
Creator-creature distinction led to a serious theological controversy in the 1940’s. The best analysis of the controversy is
that of John Frame,15 who defines the issues clearly and points the way to a solution.
Frame outlines in detail the continuities and
discontinuities between the knowledge of God and man. He shows that Van Til and Clark can be reconciled by a more
nuanced and exact consideration of
the issues. Among other things, it becomes clear that if knowledge in God is a systematically related network of truth — which
is what the equal ultimacy and thorough integration of the one and the many in God implies — then quantitative
difference without qualitative
difference is not really conceivable. If, for example, man knows “a” and “b”
and their relations, the addition of
one more point of knowledge “c,” complicates the knowledge of “a” and “b” as well, for “c” is presumably
related to each of them and may be related also to the relations between them. For man to be ignorant of
“c” means that his knowledge of “a” and “b” cannot be the same as God’s. Thus, quantitative
difference between God’s knowledge and man’s necessarily implies qualitative difference as
well.
Eschatology illumes this point from a slightly
different perspective. If the Triune God, whose being transcends our comprehension, created all things and
controls all things in terms of a
plan that reveals His glory, then all knowledge is complicated by the fact that
it holds a place in the unfolding
plan of God. We certainly cannot know how each and every fact is part of
the whole system, but if all facts
are part of God’s plan, then each and every fact does have a place in the whole. However, the whole itself cannot be
known until the end of history. Before then, I could not possibly know the full implications of any fact. But of
course, the end of history does not
mean the end of the meaning of history. Therefore, because history flows into
eternity and its relevance is not
self-enclosed, I will not be able to know the full implications of any fact
even at the end of history. Add to this what we said above, that every fact is
part of a system in which all facts
are integrated. Facts that we may never come to know in the whole course of
human history or that will not
become apparent until near the end of the process may significantly qualify facts we do know — changing our
perspective in ways that may be more important than we can imagine from our place in the unfolding
process.
Thinking about the issues of knowledge in this
way could lead to skepticism. And if there were no revelation from God, skepticism would not appear altogether
absurd. But God has revealed Himself
in Scripture and in all the creation. Even though we cannot know any fact
15 The Doctrine of
the Knowledge of God (Phillipsburg,
N.J.: Presbyterian and Reformed, 1987), pp. 19ff.
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
wholly, we can have true
knowledge, for God has revealed Himself to us and told us what is true. When
a father says to his little child that eating fruit is good for him, the child
can believe the father and accept his words as
true. He can obey his father and eat the fruit with a child’s level of
understanding. But of course, the father has things in mind that the child will
not be aware of for many years. Does that mean
the child does not really know? Not at all, he trusts his father and
knows because his father told him so. In the same way, knowledge for man who
has been created in the image of the Trinitarian God can only be
limited knowledge. To know anything at all
truly, man must become like a little child and cheerfully trust in the Word of
his heavenly Father. When he does this, he obtains knowledge
which is true, but not exhaustive.
Of course, the best illustration here is the
doctrine of the Trinity itself. It is not possible for us to conceive what it really means for unity and
diversity to be equally ultimate, no matter what formula we use to express the doctrine of the Trinity. It is commonly
said that the assertion that God is
one in one sense — being — and three in another sense — personhood — involves
no contradiction. No doubt that is
true. But that still does not make the idea comprehensible. For there to be one God who is at the same time three
Persons is unfathomable. It transgresses the “rule” of creation that one personal being is one person. It sounds to
the non-Christian like the assertion
of a transcendent multiple personality disorder. The Christian believes the
doctrine of the Trinity because
Scripture teaches it, and in Scripture, we have heard the voice of our heavenly Father speaking to us with infallible
authority. We trust the Scripture and its teaching because we are not able not
to trust it. We confess that we are confronted with mystery, but the mystery is not a burden to the believer. We see
the mystery of Triune God not only as beautiful in itself and thoroughly rational, but also as the only possible ground
for beauty and rationality.
Analogy
The incomprehensibility of God and His plan is the
ultimate reason for Van Til to conclude that man’s knowledge is “analogical.” Our knowledge is partial, based
upon what God has revealed in both
special and general revelation, but it may be true to the degree that it
conforms with God’s self-revelation.
It cannot be qualitatively the same as God’s knowledge. It can only be like God’s knowledge. This brings us
back to the controversy between Van Til and Gordon Clark. For Clark, the idea that our knowledge is
qualitatively different — analogical rather than univocal — means that we
really cannot know anything.
Frame offered
a solution to the differences that arose between Van Til and Clark suggesting in detail how God’s knowledge and
man’s differ and concur. First, the knowledge of God and man differ in the following respects.16
1.
God’s thoughts are uncreated and
eternal. Ours are created.
2.
God’s thoughts ultimately
determine what comes to pass. He causes truth by what He thinks
to be truth. Our thoughts do not.
3.
God’s thoughts are
self-validating. They serve as their own criteria of truth. Our thoughts
can never be self-attesting.
4. God’s
thoughts always bring Him glory and honor. Our thoughts bring glory and honor only
to the degree that they win His blessing.
16 The
following list is a simplified form of the list in John Frame, The Doctrine
of the Knowledge of God, pp. 22-25. The items on the list are
the same as Frame’s. It may be that by simplifying I have accidentally
distorted Frame’s points. But the essential ideas are clear
enough, I believe, even in abbreviated form.
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
5.
God’s thoughts are original. Ours
at best are copies.
6.
God does not know by revelation.
We can only know by revelation.
7.
God has not revealed all truth to
us. Our knowledge is therefore partial.
8. God possesses
knowledge in different ways from us. He is immaterial and therefore not dependent upon sense perception. He does not
reason through a process of induction or deduction. He does not forget. His knowledge has been described as an
“eternal intuition.”
9. God reveals truth to
us in creaturely terms. We do not assume that His knowledge is limited by the constraints of human language, for
example.
10. God’s thoughts all
together constitute perfect wisdom. They agree with one another in a complete and perfect system. This cannot be true
of our thoughts.
11. God’s knowledge is
“qualitatively” different. We may know what He has revealed to us, but even that knowledge fills us with wonder and
awe. What we know instead of giving us
the sense that we have fathomed all fills is with a deep sense of our
inadequacy and His greatness.
12. There are other ways,
no doubt, that God’s knowledge differs from ours, ways we cannot specify simply because He is transcendent
and beyond our reach. We could not fully
expound God’s knowledge unless we could comprehend it.
Frame
also suggested a list of continuities between our knowledge and God’s.
1.
God’s knowledge and man’s are
bound to the same standard of truth.
2. God and man think
about the same objects, including the same propositions. I know that Jesus rose from the dead. God knows the same
truth.
3. Man’s knowledge may be true in the sense that it will not
mislead him. In this sense, also, God’s
knowledge is true.
4. Man knows all sorts of things. There is reflection of
God’s omniscience in the breadth of human
knowledge.
5. We know other things
by knowing ourselves. This reflects God’s knowledge in that He knows all things
through the knowledge of Himself. There is something similar between our knowledge and His in this respect also.
6. God’s knowledge as
self-attesting is reflected in the fact that we choose the norms for knowledge that we submit to.
7. Our knowledge
reflects God’s creativity in a secondary sort of way. When we “know” something that is a lie, it has ramifications in
the world. It changes our own minds and the relationships we have with others.
When Frame says that God’s
knowledge and our both may have the same object, the point seems
to be that there is a very real, even though limited, sense in which we can
speak of God’s knowledge and man’s being
univocal. What Frame does, I think, is suggest limits to univocality. God knows that 1+1=2.
Insofar as we are only speaking of the bare proposition, man’s knowledge and God’s may be univocal. However,
nothing but epistemological bias suggests that God knows any single proposition in the simple way that we do. By
pointing out the essentially multifaceted
character of knowledge, Frame helps the reader understand what Van Til means by
affirming that our knowledge is analogous
to God’s and why Van Til prefers not to speak of univocal knowledge.
It seems to me that Frame’s
discussion could have gone further in consideration of the Trinitarian
character of God’s knowledge. For example, when we speak of God’s knowledge, it
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
is important to remember that the
Father, Son, and Holy Spirit mutually indwell one another. Whatever
one Person knows, He knows in fellowship with the other two. When we think of God’s
knowledge as self-attesting and self-validating, we should think of the
Trinitarian character of God’s knowledge. For everything that
God knows, there are three witnesses whose knowledge
is altogether consistent.
At the same time, Father, Son and Spirit have
different perspectives on the things they share. The Father, Son, and Spirit all know the cross and they all know
it in multiple ways. Their mutual
indwelling means that the Father’s knowledge of the cross includes sharing the Son’s knowledge, but the full and complete
sharing of all things through mutual indwelling must not be thought to rule out the reality of their
distinct perspectives, for that would eliminate the meaning of their personhood. Only the Son
actually experienced death for sin. Only the Father actually experienced the self-sacrificial pain of
giving the Son. Only the Spirit suffered with the Son by indwelling the Son and enabling the Son to
suffer.
How is it that by virtue of their mutual
indwelling the three Persons share all things without limit, without defect, without mystery, while at the same time
they also have something that might
be called an individual perspective? We are simply confronting the mystery of
the Trinity, the incomprehensibility of the one and the many, in another realm.
We are back to the place that we can
only confess and adore. This is part of what Frame is referring to in point 11
of his exposition of the differences between God’s knowledge and ours, but
Frame has not brought in the
Trinitarian dimension. Doing so would have clarified the social character of human knowledge and added another perspective on
the similarities and differences between our knowledge and God’s. In fact, the Trinity probably can and should be
related to each of the points in
Frame’s list. His discussion is excellent, but it is more of a stepping stone
than a destination.
Logic
If Christian faith is Trinitarian, Van Til claims,
then the Christian doctrine of logic must be different from the non-Christian.17 This does not mean that
Christians deny induction or the law of
non-contradiction. In fact, Van Til would insist that it is only within the
context of Christian confession that
these “laws” can be saved from self-destructive irrelevance. If God is true, a
God who never lies or contradicts
Himself, then what is called “the law of contradiction” is simply a description of His character.
It
is not difficult to bring the whole discussion of logic into a Trinitarian
context and restate the “laws” of
thought as descriptions of the faithfulness and honesty that subsists in the mutual love of the Persons of the Trinity. The
problem with the laws of logic as they are traditionally conceived and applied is that they are often used as a
standard by which to judge God and
His self-revelation. The issue here is obvious. If God’s knowledge transcends
ours in ways we cannot altogether
define or even comprehend, then the laws of logic, however legitimate they may be in a limited way, cannot be
applied as a limit to God’s self-revelation. The very attempt to limit God’s revelation by the laws of logic would
be an attempt to erase the distinction
between God and man and between God’s knowledge and man’s.
17 Vern
Poythress deals with the laws of logic in an important article in the Westminster
Journal, “Reforming Ontology and Logic in the Light of
the Trinity: An Application of Van Til’s Idea of Analogy,” vol. 57, no. 1,
Spring 1995, pp. 187-220.
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
Those who deny the Trinity appeal to the laws of
logic. And it is presumably because of the
logical difficulties of the doctrine of the Trinity that most apologists prefer
to argue for the existence of God,
without reference to the doctrine of the Trinity. Van Til, however, by
insisting on a Trinitarian approach
to knowledge, in effect gives the enemies of the truth a greater field for play. He not only brings up the mystery of the
Trinity from the beginning, he also claims that apparent contradiction is hiding under the covers of every fact and
truth. It only requires sufficient
investigation and consideration for us to come to the place that we confront
the limits of our understanding.
Because the world was created and is ruled by the God who is one and many, and because every fact and truth is
conditioned by its place in His perfect plan, there is mystery in all things.
The specter of contradiction haunts the whole realm of knowledge and no laws of logic can exorcise it.
What is the point of the laws of logic, then? The
laws of logic are tools that help us think, not standards to which God’s revelation must
submit. Used as tools in submission to the truth of Scripture and revelation, the laws of logic help
us to think like God thinks, since rightly understood they are simply
expositions of the faithfulness and love that characterize the communication of the Persons of the Trinity. When
we trust His faithfulness in our thought and therefore submit to the truth of His revelation, even when we cannot
fathom it, we are imitating, on a creaturely level, the perfect trust of the
Persons of the Trinity for one another. In the case of the Persons of God,
perfect trust is united with perfect mutual indwelling, an interior sharing of their thoughts and an absolute mutual
understanding that we cannot attain. The indwelling of the Spirit of God in us does, however, bring to us
something of the fellowship of the truth that appertains within the Trinity. Logic as a tool of thought can enrich
our fellowship with God and lead to a
deeper enjoyment of His truth, as an idol, it undermines not only our
relationship with God, but all
knowledge.
Trinitarian Apologetics
Van Til offered an approach to Christian
apologetics that was new in two important respects. First, he adopted the
Kantian transcendental form of argumentation to Christian apologetics. I
describe this briefly in the following section. Second, what is most important
about his transcendental argument is that Van Til presents the Triune God
Himself as the transcendent ground of
knowledge. Christian apologetics traditionally argued for the existence of “God,” not the Triune God. Van Til was the
first theologian in modern times to place Trinitarianism at the very center of Christian apologetics. Even if his
attempted form of argumentation is
not considered successful, his insistence that we argue for the Trinitarian God
from the beginning has revolutionary
implications for apologetics.
Transcendental
Argumentation
Van
Til recommended the use of a transcendental argument to prove the truth of Christianity. A transcendental argument is thought
to differ in structure from a deductive argument 18 of the sort used by the Enlightenment
rationalists, who attempted to deduce
18 This
is debatable. Not everyone agrees that the transcendental form of argument
actually works or is really distinct from other sorts of
argumentation.
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
knowledge from self-evident
truths. The problem with the rationalist approach became evident when philosophers
like Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz came to radically different conclusions. Self-evident
truths and the deductions that can be legitimately inferred from them did not
lead to a commonly recognizable truth. In contrast to the
rationalists, empiricists like Locke recommended that the house of
knowledge be built up from the foundations of common sense and
observation. Empirical verification was thought to be the test of truth.
However, this method, too, led to embarrassingly different results. Not only
that, as an epistemological methodology, it failed its own
test for knowledge. There is no empirical method for testing the truth
of the proposition that truth can only be known by observation and verified
empirically.
For the philosopher David Hume, this predicament
led to systematic skepticism, a conclusion
that deeply troubled Immanuel Kant.
Human reason has this peculiar
fate that in one species of its knowledge it is burdened
by questions which, as prescribed by the very nature of reason itself, it is
not able to ignore, but which as transcending all its powers, it is also not
able to answer.19
Greg Bahnsen, who has provided the most
exhaustive introduction to Van Til’s apologetic, summarizes, “It was scandalous, said Kant, to philosophy and human
reason that ‘if anyone thinks good to
doubt’ the existence and nature of things outside us, ‘we are unable to counter
his doubts by any satisfactory
proof’ and must accept those things ‘merely on faith.’”20 Kant proposed a new method for approaching the basic
problems of knowledge, a “Copernican revolution”
in perspective. Rather than trying to find a new answer, Kant changed the
question. Kant’s question was, in
Bahnsen’s words, “Under what conditions is it possible, or what would also need to be true in order for it to be
possible, to make sense of one’s experience of the world? To seek the transcendental conditions for knowing
is to ask what is presupposed by any intelligible
experience whatsoever.”21
What does this means in concrete terms? What does
it mean to say that the transcendental argument
asks about preconditions necessary for any knowledge, not simply the basis for
some single fact or set of truths?
Let us consider the example of two antithetical propositions.
1.
Jesus Christ
must have risen from the dead.
2.
Jesus Christ could not possibly
have risen from the dead.
The transcendental approach that
Kant introduced and Van Til endorses as a method does not
directly address these two propositions, or attempt to deductively or
inductively prove one or the other. Kant asks: what kind of
a world makes either of these propositions rationally
19
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, quoted in Greg L. Bahnsen, Van
Til’s Apologetic: Readings and Analysis
(Phillipsburg, NJ: Presbyterian and Reformed, 1998), p. 498. My entire
discussion of the transcendental argument is heavily dependent on Bahnsen’s
presentation, beginning on page 496.
20
Van Til’s Apologetic, p. 498.
21
Ibid., p. 499. Bahnsen points out that Van Til utterly rejected Kant’s specific
method for justifying knowledge. It was his general
method, his approach, that Van Til considered legitimate. Just as it would be inaccurate and odd to
accuse everyone who relies on deduction of compromise with Aristotle, it is not
true to the facts to accuse Van Til of being
tainted with Kantianism.
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
conceivable? Van Til believes
that Kant has asked the right kind of question. The answer, according
to Van Til, is that we could only make rational sense out of either of these
propositions if Christianity is true. Thus, in order for the
second proposition to be able to meaningfully communicate,
it must be false. Neither the assertion of the resurrection nor the denial of
the resurrection make sense unless the resurrection is true.
If this argument can be successfully made, it is obviously quite
powerful. However, it is easier asserted than demonstrated.
Van Til never spells out his argument in detail.
John Frame expressed doubt that the transcendental
approach to argumentation is in reality different from traditional forms of argument, except in the way things are stated. In
other words, according to Frame, it is a different form, not really a wholly different approach. Whatever can be
stated in the form of a transcendental
argument can be restated in deductive form as well. Also, David Byron, on the Van Til email list, pointed out that in order for
Van Til’s argument to stand, the Christian and the non-Christian would have to agree on the
preconditions for knowledge.22 Since all men reason in terms of their basic worldview, this hardly
seems likely. In addition, even if we supposed that the Christian and the non-Christian could agree
on the transcendental conditions for knowledge, there is nothing to prevent the non-Christian from simply setting up his
own imitation religion, borrowing
whatever preconditions for knowledge that the Christian may define.
Though the debate is not yet over, it seems
likely that Van Til’s transcendental argument cannot accomplish as much as Van Til intended. Van Til sought an
argument that was rational, not
fideistic, one which could demonstrate the truth of Christianity, not merely
its probable truth, which is as far
as traditional apologetics attempted. My own tentative conclusion is based upon
the fact that man, being finite,
must reason by faith. He cannot in the nature of the case intuitively grasp the whole realm of truth and
directly know the answers to the ultimate questions that he faces. As Kant said, we face problems that
transcend all our powers. At the same time, being made in the image of God, man has the god-like power of choosing
what he will believe. In a secondary way, by deciding to believe in a
particular religion or view of the world, he is creating his own world. No argument therefore can compel man, for
he is the image of God and can
choose his own truth. This does not mean that the argument for Christianity is
not rational, nor does it suggest
that Christianity is only probably true. It means that argumentation
cannot transcend the worldview
framework in which it functions.
Finally, we have to also keep in mind that truth
is personal and God has revealed Himself. Non-Christian men are not ignorant of God nor can they escape the
totally personal revelation of the Triune God, for the one True God reveals
Himself in and around the non-Christian man, too. This means that when we reason with non-Christian
men, we are not talking to them about a God they do not know nor are we trying to prove a truth that they cannot
comprehend. Their worldviews blind
them only in so far as they prefer darkness to the light shining all around
them.
Trinitarian
Apologetics
Whatever we may think about the problems of the
transcendental argument, we must not miss
the specifically Trinitarian nature of Van Til’s apologetic — something which
might be lost in the debate about the
validity of the transcendental argument. Because the ancient philosophical problem of the one and the many
lies at the heart of every major epistemological
22 http://members.tripod.com/~vantillian/david-byron.html This
site contains David Byron’s archives in which
Byron deals with many issues relevant to Van Til’s theology and apologetics.
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
dilemma and because its solution
is found only in the Trinity, Van Til emphasized the significance
of the Trinity for apologetics. As he shows, the problem of the one and the
many relates to questions about the relationship of change
and stability, chance and determinism, facts and
laws, love and logic — which means that an apologetic which emphasizes the
problem of the one and the many actually has a
broad range. It is not at all limited to issues of ultimate metaphysical
import.
This approach makes Van Til radically different.
Most apologists save the doctrine of the Trinity for last, after attempting to prove that theism is highly
likely, a more reasonable belief than
atheism. Having demonstrated the likelihood of theism, they move on to the next
argument, the proof that the Bible is
true, or that Jesus really did rise from the dead, or whatever, thus building the house of Christian truth block by
block. Van Til criticizes this approach as “blockhouse” methodology. Epistemologically, it should be clear that no
one actually reasons in the way
traditional apologetics approaches the proofs of Christianity. It is an
entirely hypothetical procedure. We
do not acquire truths one at a time, outside the context of a religious worldview. Van Til’s critique of traditional
apologetics is a critique of the whole Enlightenment approach to reasoning and argumentation, as well
as a critique of Thomas Aquinas23 and his modern followers.
Instead of attempting to address the basic issues
in metaphysics, epistemology, and ethics as independent problems, Van Til challenges the non-Christian worldview
as a whole. He proposes a single
argument with two sides — allow me to emphasize that it is not two different arguments, but simply two sides to one coin. There
is no special order, therefore, in which the argument should be stated, and since Van Til is interested in worldview
as a whole, it doesn’t really matter
what particular issue the conversation between Christian and non-Christian
begins with or focuses on.
Everything is related. Whatever the non-Christian is interested in, whatever he
or she wishes to talk about, that is the point where the conversation may
begin. Van Til does not have to wait
for the non-Christian to be willing to talk about God, or the Bible, or the resurrection.
With that in mind, let us look briefly at his
double-barreled argument. First, there is a negative side. In this, Van Til offers an internal critique of whatever
non-Christian worldview he is dealing
with. All non-Christian worldviews break down when they confront the problem of
the one and the many, but few
non-Christian thinkers address the problem directly. Van Til shows how the issues they do address relate to
the problem of the one and the many, and then demonstrates how their viewpoint
crumbles because of inconsistencies and arbitrariness.
Second,
the positive side of Van Til’s approach attempts to show the non-Christian how Christianity offers a solution to the problems his
view faces, one which is grounded in the knowledge of the Christian God. He
invites the non-Christian to stand on Christian ground for the sake of argument. He presents the Christian
worldview as a whole, showing how it answers issues that the non-Christian
worldview cannot. The aim of the positive side of the apologetic argument (presentation) is broader than just the
solution to particular problems. Van Til seeks to demonstrate that the Triune God is “the only
possible presupposition for the possibility of predication.”24 The only adequate argument, according to Van
Til, is one which establishes that Christianity
alone offers a truly rational ground for knowledge and life. Here, as we
pointed out
23 I mean a critique of Aquinas as traditionally
understood. There is a real question about whether either Roman Catholic or Protestant thinkers have done
justice to Aquinas, but that is not relevant to the present issue.
24 Introduction to Systematic Theology,
p. 229.
Van
Til’s Insights on the Trinity
above, some find that his
argument may fall short. But the idea of presenting Christianity in its fullness
as a worldview is important, whether it constitutes what has been traditionally
regarded as a rational argument or not. To state this in different
words, whether or not Van Til was able to accomplish
his aim of establishing an argument for Christianity that gives rationally
compelling proof that Christianity alone provides the necessary
preconditions for knowledge, he certainly did succeed in showing
the comprehensive importance of the doctrine of the Trinity for the Christian worldview. His
method of internal critique is simply showing how non-Christian thought
breaks down because it lacks the Triune God at the heart of its system. A Van
Tillian internal critique of a non-Christian system of thought
might be termed a Trinitarian critique. When
he offers a positive presentation of the Christian worldview, he always places
the doctrine of the Trinity — or, better, the Triune God of
love Himself — in the central position of his argument,
for everything in the Christian worldview goes back to the question of God.
Trinity and Covenant in Van Til
Van Til seldom emphasized the
covenantal nature of the Trinity and as far as I can tell his expositors
have not given it attention as an aspect of his system. Van Til did make at
least one quite explicit statement of the covenantal
character of the Trinitarian relationships and implied a covenantal
relationship in other places. Since he was a diligent student of Abraham
Kuyper, it seems likely that Van Til picked up his view of
the covenant among the Persons of the Trinity through
Kuyper’s writings. Be that as it may, Van Til’s doctrine of the Trinity
included two ideas which both point to covenantal relationships
among the persons of the Trinity. First, Van Til
spoke of the traditional notion of perichoresis in language that seems
distinctly covenantal. Second, Van Til spoke of
covenantal representation in language that explicitly shows that he saw such
representation in the relationships of the Persons of the Trinity.
Indwelling
and Covenant
Perichoresis is
the traditional word to describe the mutual indwelling of the Persons of the Trinity.
Van Til expressed this indwelling as the persons of the Trinity being “mutually
exhaustive of one another.” For Van Til, the mutual
indwelling of the Persons of the Trinity means the Three “have one mind and
will” and “a common consciousness.”25 Cornelius Plantinga
speaks in similar language.
Each member is a distinct person, but scarcely an
individual or separate person. For in the divine life there is no
isolation, no insulation, no secretiveness, no fear of being
transparent to another. Hence there may be penetrating, inside knowledge of the
other as other, but as co-other, loved other, fellow. Father, Son, and Spirit
are ‘members one of another’ to a superlative degree. . . . There is in the
divine life a mysterious, primordial in-ness or oneness relation
that is short of a oneness of person but much closer than mere common
membership in a class.26
25 An Introduction to Systematic
Theology (Phillipsburg, N.J.:
Presbyterian and Reformed, 1978), p. 220.
26
Cornelius Plantinga, Jr., "The Threeness/Oneness Problem of the
Trinity," Calvin Theological Journal, 23, no. 1
(April, 1988), pp. 50-51.
Van Til’s Insights
on the Trinity
Though Plantinga and Van Til do
not use the word “covenant,” they are both describing the
community life of God that is grounded in the covenantal bond. Van Til often
refers to the three Persons of the Trinity being “mutually
exhaustive” of one another, that is, indwelling one another
so perfectly that each is wholly known to and open to the others. While he does
not unambiguously state that perichoresis is a
covenantal truth, Van Til is clear about representation being
covenantal and the similarity of the language that he uses to speak of perichoresis
and representation suggests that he may have regarded them both as expressions
of a covenantal relationship among the Persons of
the Godhead.
Representation
and Covenant
To restate the point: since for
Van Til, the notions of representation and indwelling seem to be
related and representation is a covenantal notion, it seems probable that in
Van Til’s thought indwelling is a covenantal notion also. In
any case, Van Til expounded the notion of representation
in a manner that implied that God’s covenant with man reflects a covenant among
the Persons of the Trinity.
It were quite legitimate and
true to say that the foundation of all personal activity among
men must be based upon the personality of one ultimate person, namely, the person
of God, if only it be understood that this ultimate personality of God is a triune
personality. In the Trinity there is completely personal relationship without residue.
And for that reason it may be said that man’s actions are all personal too.
Man’s surroundings are shot through with personality because all things are
related to the infinitely personal God. But when we have said
that the surroundings of man are really completely
personalized, we have also established the fact of the representational
principle. All of man’s acts must be representational of the acts of God.
Even the persons of the Trinity are mutually representational. They are exhaustively
representational of one another. Because he is a creature, man must, in his
thinking, his feeling and his willing, be representative of God. There is no
other way open for him. He could, in the nature of the case,
think nothing at all unless he thought God’s thoughts after him, and this is
representational thinking. Thus man’s thought
is representative of God’s thought, but not exhaustively representative.
The doctrine of original sin is
based upon this purely theistic, because purely biblical, concept
of representation. Since the whole being of God, if we may in all reverence say
so, is built upon the representational plan, it was impossible for God to
create except upon the representational plan.27
In another place, Van Til states that the notion of the
Persons of the Trinity being mutually representational
is the very essence of the covenantal idea.
It
may even be said that Calvin’s covenantal idea is Theism come to its own.
The
covenant idea is nothing but the
representational principle consistently applied to all
27 A
Survey of Christian Epistemology (Phillipsburg, NJ: Presbyterian
and Reformed, no date), pp. 78-79. Paraphrasing Van Til, we might say that
since the whole being of God is built upon the covenantal plan, it was impossible
for God to create except on the covenantal plan.
Van Til’s Insights
on the Trinity
reality. The foundation of the
representational principle among men is the fact that the Trinity exists in the
form of a mutually exhaustive representation of the three Persons
that constitute it. The emphasis should be placed upon the idea of exhaustion.
This is important because it brings out the point of the complete equality as
far as ultimacy is concerned of the principle of unity and of diversity. This
mutual exhaustion of the persons of the Trinity places one
before the choice of interpreting reality in exclusively temporal
categories or in eternal categories. The demand of the doctrine of the Trinity,
when thus conceived is that reality be interpreted in exclusively eternal categories inasmuch as the source of diversity lies
in the Trinity itself and could never be found in a sense world beyond God.
Hence the problem of the one and the
many, of the universal and the particular, of being and becoming, of analytical and synthetic reasoning, of the a
priori and the a posteriori must be solved by an exclusive reference to the Trinity.28
Van Til’s emphasis here on the
exhaustive nature of the representation of the Persons of the Trinity is
precisely the sort of emphasis seen in his statements on the mutual indwelling
of the Persons of the Trinity; the two seem obviously
related.29 Because the Persons of the Trinity mutually
indwell one another, perfectly and wholly, they also mutually represent one
another. This, according to Van Til, is the essence of the
covenant. Van Til did not develop this into a systematic
doctrine or attempt to integrate it into the whole of his theology. But the
fact that it appears in his writings is worthy of note.
Conclusion
Van Til offered important
contributions to Trinitarian theology. Each of the five areas above
suggest significant insights into the doctrine of the Trinity, insights that
are not necessarily original with Van Til but which
he stated in his own original manner in the context of his own specific
approach. Van Til appears to be re-phrasing Charles Hodge, for example, when he
refers to God as one Person and three Persons. But Hodge
did not employ the intentionally paradoxical language that Van Til did. Van Til is probably
borrowing his notion of the Trinitarian
covenant from Abraham Kuyper, but the emphasis on representation is, so far as
I can tell, new.30 While
it is hard to imagine that there is no one in the history of the Church prior
to Van Til that has specifically
related the doctrine of the Trinity to the Greek philosophical problem of the one and the many, there is
certainly no one before Van Til that brought much attention to the issue.
However,
Van Til’s greatest contribution, in my opinion, is not to be found in any of
these specific insights themselves, but rather in the fact
that he insisted that the Triune God Himself must
be the true center of our theology and apologetics. Bare theism and every form
of impersonalism and abstract thought are rejected. Van Til
claims that the only God who can be
28 A
Survey of Christian Epistemology, p. 96. He goes on to say, “It
was upon this foundation of a truly Trinitarian concept that Calvin
built his conception of covenant theology.” P. 97.
29 See: The
Defense of the Faith (Phillipsburg, NJ: Presbyterian and Reformed, 1967, 3rd
revised edition), p. 25, and An Introduction to Systematic Theology (Phillipsburg,
NJ: Presbyterian and Reformed, 1974), pp. 220 ff.
30 Van Til read Kuyper in Dutch, of course, giving him access to much
more material than I can check.
Van Til’s Insights on
the Trinity
wholly Personal God is
the Tri-personal God of the Bible. It was Van Til’s emphasis on the Trinity that has passed on to his heirs. Because
of Van Til’s teaching, men like John Frame offer Trinitarian systematic theology and apologetics, James Jordan offers a
new and distinctly Trinitarian
approach to Biblical, systematic, and practical theology, and Vern Poythress
offers a Trinitarian approach to
mathematics, philosophy of science, linguistics and hermeneutics — to name only a few prominent men who have been
influenced by Van Til. The doctrine of the Triune God is again being seen to be the heart of the Christian
worldview, with the advantage that
we not only have a God-centered system of thought, but one that makes
fellowship in the family of God,
faith, and worship epistemologically fundamental. This is Van Til’s legacy.